BestLightNovel.com

The History of Creation Volume I Part 10

The History of Creation - BestLightNovel.com

You’re reading novel The History of Creation Volume I Part 10 online at BestLightNovel.com. Please use the follow button to get notification about the latest chapter next time when you visit BestLightNovel.com. Use F11 button to read novel in full-screen(PC only). Drop by anytime you want to read free – fast – latest novel. It’s great if you could leave a comment, share your opinion about the new chapters, new novel with others on the internet. We’ll do our best to bring you the finest, latest novel everyday. Enjoy

Divergent adaptation can very easily be perceived among plants, especially in creepers. Branches of one and the same creeping plant, which originally were formed alike, acquire a completely different form and extent, a completely different degree of curvature and diameter of spiral winding, according as they twine themselves round a thinner or a thicker bar. The divergent change of form of parts originally identical in form, which tending in different directions develop themselves under different external conditions, can be distinctly demonstrated in many other examples. As this divergent adaptation interacts with progressive inheritance, it becomes the cause of a division of labour among the different organs.

An eighth and last law of adaptation we may call _the law of unlimited or infinite adaptation_. By it we simply mean to express that we know of no limit to the variation of organic forms occasioned by the external conditions of existence. We can a.s.sert of no single part of an organism, that it is no longer variable, or that if it were subjected to new external conditions it would not be changed by them. It has never yet been proved by experience that there is a limit to variation. If, for example, an organ degenerates from non-use, this degeneration ends finally in a complete disappearance of the organ, as is the case with the eyes of many animals. On the other hand, we are able, by continual practice, habit, and the ever-increasing use of an organ, to bring it to a degree of perfection which we should at the beginning have considered to be impossible. If we compare the uncivilized savages with civilized nations, we find among the former a development of the organs of sense-sight, smell, and hearing-such as civilized nations can hardly conceive of. On the other hand, the brain, that is mental activity, among more civilized nations is developed to a degree of which the wild savages have no idea.

There appears indeed to be a limit given to the adaptability of every organism, by the "type" of its tribe or phylum; that is, by the essential fundamental qualities of this tribe, which have been inherited from a common ancestor, and transmitted by conservative inheritance to all its descendants. Thus, for example, no vertebrate animal can acquire the ventral nerve-chord of articulate animals, instead of the characteristic spinal marrow of the vertebrate animals. However, within this hereditary primary form, within this inalienable type, the degree of adaptability is unlimited. The elasticity and fluidity of the organic form manifests itself, within the type, freely in all directions, and to an unlimited extent. But there are some animals, as, for example, the parasitically degenerate crabs and worms, which seem to pa.s.s even the limit of type, and have forfeited all the essential characteristics of their tribe by an astonis.h.i.+ng degree of degeneration. As to the adaptability of man, it is, as in all other animals, also unlimited, and since it is manifested in him above all other animals, in the modifications of the brain, there can be absolutely no limit to the knowledge which man in a further progress of mental cultivation may not be able to exceed. The human mind, according to the law of unlimited adaptation, enjoys an infinite perspective of becoming ever more and more perfect.

These remarks are sufficient to show the extent of the phenomena of Adaptation, and the great importance to be attached to them. The laws of Adaptation, or the facts of Variation caused by the influence of external conditions, are just as important as the laws of Inheritance.

All phenomena of Adaptation, in the end, can be traced to conditions of nutrition of the organism, in the same way as the phenomena of Inheritance are referable to conditions of reproduction; but the latter, as well as the former, may further be traced to chemical and physical, that is to mechanical, causes. According to Darwin's Theory of Selection the new forms of organisms, the transformations which artificial selection produces in the state of cultivation, and which natural selection produces in the state of nature, arise solely by the interaction of such causes.

CHAPTER XI.

NATURAL SELECTION BY THE STRUGGLE FOR EXISTENCE. DIVISION OF LABOUR AND PROGRESS.

Interaction of the Two Organic Formative Causes, Inheritance and Adaptation.-Natural and Artificial Selection.-Struggle for Existence, or Compet.i.tion for the Necessaries of Life.-Disproportion between the Number of Possible or Potential, and the Number of Real or Actual Individuals.-Complicated Correlations of all Neighbouring Organisms.-Mode of Action in Natural Selection.-h.o.m.ochromic Selection as the Cause of Sympathetic Colourings.-s.e.xual Selection as the Cause of the Secondary s.e.xual Characters.-Law of Separation or Division of Labour (Polymorphism, Differentiation, Divergence of Characters).-Transition of Varieties into Species.-Idea of Species.-Hybridism.-Law of Progress or Perfectioning (Progressus, Teleosis).

In order to arrive at a right understanding of Darwinism, it is, above all, necessary that the two organic functions of _Inheritance and Adaptation_, which we spoke of in our last chapter, should be more closely examined. If we do not, on the one hand, examine the purely mechanical nature of these two physiological activities, and the various action of their different laws, and if, on the other hand, we do not consider how complicated the interaction of these different laws of Inheritance and Adaptation must be, we shall not be able to understand how these two functions, by themselves, have been able to produce all the variety of animal and vegetable forms, which, in fact, they have.

We have, at least, hitherto been unable to discover any other formative causes besides these two, and if we rightly understand the necessary and infinitely complicated interaction of Inheritance and Adaptation, we do not require to look for other unknown causes for the change of organic forms. These two fundamental causes are, as far as we can see, completely sufficient.

Even long before Darwin had published his Theory of Selection, some naturalists, and especially Goethe, had a.s.sumed the interaction of two distinct formative tendencies-a conservative or preserving, and a progressive or changing formative tendency-as the causes of the variety of organic forms. The former was called by Goethe the centripetal or specifying tendency, the latter the centrifugal tendency, or the tendency to metamorphosis (p. 89). These two tendencies completely correspond with the two processes of Inheritance and Adaptation.

_Inheritance_ is the _centripetal_ or _internal formative tendency_ which strives to keep the organic form in its species, to form the descendants like the parents, and always to produce identical things from generation to generation. _Adaptation_, on the other hand, which counteracts inheritance, is the _centrifugal_ or _external formative tendency_, which constantly strives to change the organic forms through the influence of the varying agencies of the outer world, to create new forms out of those existing, and entirely to destroy the constancy or permanency of species. Accordingly as Inheritance or Adaptation predominates in the struggle, the specific form either remains constant or changes into a new species. The degree of constancy of form in the different species of animals and plants, which obtains at any moment, is simply the necessary result of the momentary predominance which either of these two formative powers (or physiological activities) has acquired over the other.

If we now return to the consideration of the process of selection or choice, the outlines of which we have already examined, we shall be in a position to see clearly and distinctly that both artificial and natural selection rest solely upon the interaction of these two formative tendencies. If we carefully watch the proceedings of an artificial selector-a farmer or a gardener-we find that only these two constructive forces are used by him for the production of new forms. The whole art of artificial selection rests solely upon a thoughtful and wise application of the laws of Inheritance and Adaptation, and upon their being applied and regulated in an artistic and systematic manner.

Here the will of man const.i.tutes the selecting force.

The case of natural selection is quite similar, for it also employs merely these two organic constructive forces, these ingrained physiological properties of Adaptation and Heredity, in order to produce the different species. But the selecting principle or force, which in _artificial_ selection is represented by the conscious _will of man_ acting for a definite purpose, consists in _natural_ selection of the unconscious _struggle for existence_ acting without a definite plan.

What we mean by "struggle for existence" has already been explained in the seventh chapter. It is the recognition of this exceedingly important ident.i.ty which const.i.tutes one of the greatest of Darwin's merits. But as this relation is very frequently imperfectly or falsely understood, it is necessary to examine it now more closely, and to ill.u.s.trate by a few examples the operation of the struggle for life, and the operation of natural selection _by means of_ the struggle for life (Gen. Morph.

ii. 231).

When considering the struggle for life, we started from the fact that the number of germs which all animals and plants produce is infinitely greater than the number of individuals which actually come to life and remain alive for a longer or shorter time. Most organisms produce during life thousands or millions of germs, from each of which, under favourable circ.u.mstances, a new individual might arise. In most animals and plants these germs are eggs, that is cells, which for their development require s.e.xual fructification. But among the Protista, the lowest organisms, which are neither animals nor plants, and which propagate themselves only in a non-s.e.xual manner, the germ-cells, or spores, require no fructification. Now, in all cases the number of uns.e.xual, as well as of s.e.xual germs, is out of all proportion to the number of actually living individuals of every species.

Taken as a whole, the number of living animals and plants on our earth remains always about the same. The number of places in the economy of nature is limited, and in most parts of the earth's surface these places are always approximately occupied. Certainly there occur everywhere and in every year fluctuations in the absolute and in the relative number of individuals of all species. However, taken as a whole, these fluctuations are of little importance, and it is broadly the fact that the total number of all individuals remains, on an average, almost constant. There is a constant fluctuation, which depends on the fact that in one year or another one or other series of animals and plants predominates, and that every year the struggle for life somewhat alters their relations.

Every single species of animals and plants would have densely peopled the whole earth's surface in a short time, if it had not had to struggle against a number of enemies and hostile influences. Even Linnaeus calculated that if an annual plant only produced two seeds (and there is not one which produces so few), it would have yielded in twenty years a million of individuals. Darwin has calculated of elephants, which of all animals seem the slowest to increase, that in seven hundred and fifty years the descendants of a single pair would amount to nineteen millions of individuals; this is supposing that every elephant, during its period of fertility (from the 30th to the 90th year), produced only three pairs of young ones, and survived itself to its hundredth year. In like manner the increase of the number of human beings-if calculated on the average proportion of births to population, and no hindrances to the natural increase stood in the way-would be such as to double the total in twenty-five years. In every century the total number of men would have increased sixteen-fold; whereas we know that the total number of human beings increases but slowly, and that the increase of population is very different in different countries. While European tribes spread over the whole globe, other tribes or species of men every year draw nearer to their complete extinction. This is the case especially with the redskins of America, and with the copper-coloured natives of Australia. Even if these races were to propagate more abundantly than the white Europeans, yet they would sooner or later succ.u.mb to the latter in the struggle for life. But of all human individuals, as of all other organisms, by far the majority perish at the earliest period of their lives. Of the immense quant.i.ty of germs which every species produce, only very few actually succeed in developing, and of these few it is again only a very small portion which attain to the age in which they can reproduce themselves (compare p. 161).

From the disproportion between the immense excess of organic germs and the small number of chosen individuals which are actually able to continue in existence beside one another, there follows of necessity that universal struggle for life, that constant fight for existence, that perpetual compet.i.tion for the necessaries of life, of which I gave a sketch in my seventh chapter. It is this struggle for life which brings natural selection into play, which in its turn is made use of by the interaction of the phenomena of Inheritance and Adaptation as a sifting agency, and which thus causes a continual change in all organic forms. In this struggle for acquiring the necessary conditions of existence, those individuals will always overpower their rivals who possess any individual privilege, any advantageous quality, of which their fellow compet.i.tors are dest.i.tute. It is true we are able only in the fewest cases (in those animals and plants best known to us) to form an approximate conception of the infinitely complicated interaction of the numerous circ.u.mstances, all of which here come into combination.

Only think how infinitely varied and complicated are the relations of every single human being to the rest of mankind, and in general, to the whole of the surrounding outer world. But similar relations prevail also among all animals and plants which live together in one place. All influence one another actively or pa.s.sively. Every animal and every plant struggles directly with a number of enemies, beasts of prey, parasitic animals, etc. Plants standing together struggle with one another for the s.p.a.ce of ground requisite for their roots, for the necessary amount of light, air, moisture, etc. In like-manner, animals living together struggle with one another for their food, dwelling-place, etc. In this most active and complicated struggle, any personal superiority, however small, any individual advantage, may possibly decide the issue in favour of the one possessing it. This privileged individual remains the victor in the struggle, and propagates itself, while its fellow-compet.i.tors perish before they succeed in propagating themselves. The personal advantage which gave it the victory is transmitted by inheritance to its descendants, and by a further development may become so strongly marked as to cause us to consider the later generations as a new species.

The infinitely complicated correlations which exist between the organisms of every district, and which must be looked upon as the real conditions of the struggle for life, are mostly unknown to us, and are very difficult to discover. We have hitherto been able to trace them only to a certain point in individual cases, as in the example given by Darwin of the relations between cats and red clover in England. The red clover (_Trifolium pratense_), which in England is among the best fodder for cattle, requires the visit of humming-bees in order to attain the formation of seeds. These insects, while sucking the honey from the bottom of the flower, bring the pollen in contact with the stigma, and thus cause the fructification of the flower, which never takes place without it. Darwin has shown by experiments, that red clover which is not visited by humming-bees does not yield a single seed. The number of bees is determined by the number of their enemies, the most destructive of which are the field-mice. The more the field-mice predominate, the less the clover is fructified. The number of field-mice, again, is dependent upon the number of their enemies, princ.i.p.ally cats. Hence in the neighbourhood of villages and towns, where many cats are kept, there are plenty of bees. A great number of cats, therefore, is evidently of great advantage for the fructification of clover. This example may be followed still further, as has been done by Carl Vogt, if we consider that cattle which feed on red clover are one of the most important foundations of the wealth of England. Englishmen preserve their bodily and mental powers chiefly by making excellent meat-roast beef and beefsteak-their princ.i.p.al food. The English owe the superiority of their brains and minds over those of other nations in a great measure to their excellent meat. But this is clearly indirectly dependent upon the cats, which pursue the mice. We may, with Huxley, even trace the chain of causes to those old maids who cherish and keep cats, and, consequently, are of the greatest importance to the fructification of the clover and to the prosperity of England. From this example we can see that the further it is traced the wider is the circle of action and of correlation. We can with certainty maintain that there exist a great number of such correlations in every plant and in every animal, only we are not always able to point out and survey their concatenation as in the last instance.

Another remarkable example of important correlations is the following, given by Darwin. In Paraguay, there are no wild oxen and horses, as in the neighbouring parts of South America, both north and south of Paraguay. This surprising circ.u.mstance is explained simply by the fact that in that country a kind of small fly is very frequent, and is in the habit of laying its eggs in the navel of newly-born calves and foals.

The newly-born animals die in consequence of this attack, and the small deadly fly is therefore the cause of oxen and horses never becoming wild in that district. Supposing that this fly were destroyed by some insect-eating bird, then these large mammals would grow wild in Paraguay, as well as in the neighbouring parts of South America; and as they would eat a quant.i.ty of certain species of plants, the whole flora, and, consequently again, the whole fauna of the country would become changed. It is hardly necessary to state, that at the same time the whole economy, and consequently the character, of the human population would alter.

Thus the prosperity, nay, even the existence of whole populations can be indirectly determined by a single small animal or vegetable form in itself extremely insignificant. There are small coral islands whose human inhabitants live almost entirely upon the fruit of a species of palm. The fructification of this palm is princ.i.p.ally effected by insects, which carry the pollen from the male to the female palm trees.

The existence of these useful insects is endangered by insect-eating birds, which in their turn are pursued by birds of prey. The birds of prey, however, often succ.u.mb to the attack of a small parasitical mite, which develops itself in millions in their feathers. This small, dangerous parasite, again, may be killed by parasitical moulds. Moulds, birds of prey, and insects would in this case favour the prosperity of the palm, and consequently of man; birds, mites, and insect-eating birds would, on the other hand, endanger it.

Interesting examples in relation to the change of correlations in the struggle for life are furnished also by those isolated oceanic islands, uninhabited by man, on which at different times goats and pigs have been placed by navigators. These animals become wild, and having no enemies, they increase in number so excessively, that the rest of the animal and vegetable population suffer in consequence, and the island finally may become almost a waste, because there is insufficient food for the large mammals which increase too numerously. In some cases on an island thus overrun with goats and pigs, other navigators have let loose a couple of dogs, who enjoyed this superabundance of food, and they again increased so numerously, and made such havoc among the herds, that after several years the dogs themselves lacked food, and they also almost died out.

The equilibrium of species continually changes in this manner in nature's economy, accordingly as one or another species increases at the expense of the rest. In most cases the relations of different species of animals and plants to one another are much too complicated for us to be able to follow them, and I leave it to the reader to picture to himself what an infinitely complicated machinery is at work in every part of the world in consequence of this struggle. The impulses which started the struggle, and which altered and modified it in different places, are in the end seen to be the impulses of self-preservation-in fact, the instinct leading individuals to preserve themselves (the instinct of obtaining food), and the instinct leading them to preserve the species (instinct of propagation). It is these two fundamental instincts of organic self-preservation of which Schiller, the idealist (not Goethe, the realist!) says:

"Meanwhile, until philosophy Sustains the structure of the world, Her workings will be carried on By hunger and by love."[4]

It is these two powerful fundamental instincts which, by their varying activity, produce such extraordinary differences in species through the struggle for life. They are the foundations of the phenomena of Inheritance and Adaptation. We have, in fact, traced all phenomena of Inheritance to propagation, all phenomena of Adaptation to nutrition, as the two wider cla.s.ses of material phenomena to which they belong.

The struggle for life in natural selection acts with as much selective power as does the will of man in artificial selection. The latter, however, acts according to a plan and consciously, the former without a plan and unconsciously. This important difference between artificial and natural selection deserves especial consideration. For we learn by it to understand how _arrangements serving a purpose can be produced by mechanical causes acting without an object, as well as by causes acting for an object_. The products of natural selection are arranged even more for a purpose than the artificial products of man, and yet they owe their existence not to a creative power acting for a definite purpose, but to a mechanical relation acting unconsciously and without a plan.

If we had not thoroughly considered the interaction of Inheritance and Adaptation under the influence of the struggle for life, we should not at first be inclined to expect such results from this natural process of selection as are, in fact, furnished by it. It may therefore be appropriate here to mention a few especially striking examples of the activity of natural selection.

Let us first take _Darwin's h.o.m.ochromic selection_ of animals, or the so-called "sympathetic selection of colours," into consideration.

Earlier naturalists have remarked that numerous animals are of nearly the same colour as their dwelling-place, or the surroundings in which they permanently live. Thus, for example, plant-lice and many other insects living on leaves are of a green colour. The inhabitants of the deserts, the jerboa, or leaping mice, foxes of the desert, gazelles, lions, etc., are mostly of a yellow or yellowish-brown colour, like the sand of the desert. The polar animals, which live on the ice and snow, are white or grey, like ice and snow. Many of these animals change their colour in summer and winter. In summer, when the snow partly vanishes, the fur of these polar creatures becomes brownish-grey or blackish, like the naked earth, while in winter it again becomes white. b.u.t.terflies and insects which hover round the gay and bright flowers are like them in colour. Now, Darwin explains this surprising circ.u.mstance quite simply by the fact that such colours as agree with the colour of the habitation are of the greatest use to the animals concerned. If these animals are animals of prey, they will be able to approach the object of their pursuit more safely and with less likelihood of observation, and, in like manner, those animals which are pursued will be able to escape more easily, if their colour is as little different as possible from that of their surroundings. If therefore originally an animal species varied so as to present cases of all colours, those individuals whose colour most resembled the surroundings must have been most favoured in the struggle for life. They remained more un.o.bserved, maintained and propagated themselves, while those individuals or varieties differently coloured died out.

I have tried to explain, by the same sympathetic selection of colour, the wonderful fact that the majority of pelagic animals-that is, of those which live on the surface of the open sea-are bluish, or completely colourless and transparent, like gla.s.s and water itself. Such colourless, gla.s.sy animals are met with in the most different cla.s.ses.

To them belong, among fish, the Helmicthyidae, through whose crystalline bodies the words of a book can be read; among the molluscs, the finned snails (Heteropods) and sea-b.u.t.terflies, or whales-food (Pteropods); among worms, the Salpae, Alciope, and Sagitta; further, a great number of pelagic crabs (Crustacea), and the greater part of the Medusae Umbrella-jellies, (Discomedusae); Comb-jellies, (Ctenophora). All of these pelagic animals, which float on the surface of the ocean, are transparent and colourless, like gla.s.s and like the water itself, while their nearest kin live at the bottom of the ocean, and are coloured and opaque like the inhabitants of the land. This remarkable fact, like the sympathetic colouring of the inhabitants of the earth, can be explained by natural selection. Among the ancestors of the pelagic gla.s.s-like animals which showed a different degree of colourlessness and transparency, those that were the most colourless and transparent must have been most favoured in the active struggle for life which takes place on the surface of the ocean. They were enabled to approach their prey the most easily un.o.bserved, and were themselves least observed by their enemies. Hence they could preserve and propagate themselves more easily than their more coloured and opaque relatives; and finally, by acc.u.mulative adaptation and transmission by inheritance, through natural selection, in the course of many generations their bodies would attain that degree of crystal-like transparency and colourlessness which we at present admire in them. (Gen. Morph. ii. 242.)

No less interesting and instructive than h.o.m.ochromic selection is that species of natural selection which Darwin calls "_s.e.xual selection_,"

which explains the origin of the so-called "secondary s.e.xual characters." We have already mentioned these subordinate s.e.xual characteristics, so instructive in many respects. They comprise those peculiarities of animals and plants which belong only to one of the two s.e.xes, and which do not stand in any direct relation to the act of propagation itself (compare above, p. 244). Such secondary s.e.xual characters occur in great variety among animals. We all know how striking is the difference of the two s.e.xes in size and colour in many birds and b.u.t.terflies. The male s.e.x is generally the larger and more beautiful. It often possesses special decorations or weapons; as for example, the spur and comb of the c.o.c.k, the antlers of the stag and deer, etc. All these peculiarities of the two s.e.xes have nothing directly to do with propagation itself, which is effected by the "primary s.e.xual characters," or actual s.e.xual organs.

Now, the origin of these remarkable "secondary s.e.xual characters" is explained by Darwin simply by a choice or selection which takes place in the propagation of animals. In most animals the number of individuals of both s.e.xes is unequal; either the number of the female or the number of the male individuals is greater, and, as a rule, when the season of propagation approaches, a struggle takes place between the rivals for the possession of the animals of the other s.e.x. It is well known with what vigour and vehemence this struggle is fought out among the higher animals-among mammals and birds-especially among those of polygamous habits. Among gallinaceous birds, where for one c.o.c.k there are several hens, a severe struggle takes place between the competing c.o.c.ks for as large a harem as possible. The same is the case with many ruminating animals. Among stags and deer, for instance, at the period of rut, deadly struggles take place between the males for the possession of the females. The secondary s.e.xual character which here distinguishes the males-the antlers of stags and deer-not possessed by the female, is, according to Darwin, the consequence of that struggle. Here the motive and cause determining the struggle is not, as in the case of the struggle for individual existence, self-preservation, but the preservation of the species-propagation. There are numerous pa.s.sive weapons of defence, as well as active weapons for attack. The lion's mane, not possessed by the female, is evidently such a weapon of defence; it is an excellent means of protection against the bites which the male lions try to inflict on each other's necks when fighting for the females; consequently those males with the strongest manes have the greatest advantage in the s.e.xual struggle. The dewlap of the ox and the comb of the c.o.c.k are similar defensive weapons. Active weapons of attack, on the other hand, are the antlers of the stag, the tusks of the boar, the spur of the c.o.c.k, and the hugely developed pair of jaws in the male stag-beetle; all are instruments employed by the males in the struggle for the females, for annihilating or chasing away their rivals.

In the cases just mentioned, it is the bodily "struggle to the death"

which determines the origin of the secondary s.e.xual characters. But, besides these mortal struggles, there are other important compet.i.tions in s.e.xual selection, which no less influence the structure of the rivals. These consist princ.i.p.ally in the fact that the courting s.e.x tries to please the other by external finery, by beauty of form, or by a melodious voice. Darwin thinks that the beautiful voices of singing birds have princ.i.p.ally originated in this way. Many male birds carry on a regular musical contest when they contend for the possession of the females. It is known of several singing birds, that in the breeding season the males a.s.semble in numbers round the females, and let their songs resound before them, and that then the females choose the singers who best please them for their mates. Among other songsters, individual males pour out their songs in the loneliness of the forest in order to attract the females, and the latter follow the most attractive calls. A similar musical contest, though certainly less melodious, takes place among crickets and gra.s.shoppers. The male cricket has on its belly two instruments like drums, and produces with these the sharp chirping notes which the ancient Greeks curiously enough thought beautiful music. Male gra.s.shoppers, partly by using their hind-legs like the bow of a violin against their wing coverings, and partly by rubbing their wing coverings together, bring out tones which are, indeed, not melodious to us, but which please the female gra.s.shoppers so much that they choose the male who fiddles the best.

Among other insects and birds it is not song or, in fact, any musical accomplishment, but finery or beauty of the one s.e.x which attracts the other. Thus we find that, among most gallinaceous birds, the c.o.c.ks are distinguished by combs on their heads, or by a beautiful tail, which they can spread out like a fan; as for example, in the case of the peac.o.c.k and turkey-c.o.c.k. The magnificent tail of the bird of paradise is also an exclusive ornament of the male s.e.x. In like manner, among very many other birds and very many insects, princ.i.p.ally among b.u.t.terflies, the males are distinguished from the females by special colours or other decorations. These are evidently the results of s.e.xual selection. As the females do not possess these attractions and decorations, we must come to the conclusion that they have been acquired by degrees by the males in the compet.i.tion for the females, which takes its origin in the selective discrimination of the females.

We may easily picture to ourselves, in detail, the application of this interesting conclusion to the human community. Here, also, the same causes have evidently influenced the development of the secondary s.e.xual characters. The characteristics distinguis.h.i.+ng the man, as well as those distinguis.h.i.+ng the woman, owe their origin, certainly for the most part, to the s.e.xual selection of the other s.e.x. In antiquity and in the Middle Ages, especially in the romantic age of chivalry, it was the bodily struggles to the death-the tournaments and duels-which determined the choice of the bride; the strongest carried home the bride. In more recent times, however, in our so-called "polished" or "highly civilized" society, competing rivals prefer to contend indirectly by means of musical accomplishments, instrumental performances and song, by bodily charms, natural beauty, or artificial decoration. But by far the most important of these different forms of s.e.xual selection in man is that form which is the most exalted, namely, _psychical selection_, in which the mental excellencies of the one s.e.x influence and determine the choice of the other. The most highly intellectually developed types of men have, throughout generations, when choosing a partner in life, been guided by her excellencies of soul, and have thus transmitted these qualities to their posterity, and they have in this way, more than by any other thing, helped to create the deep chasm which at present separates civilized men from the rudest savages, and from our common animal ancestors. In fact, both the part played by the prevalence of a higher standard of s.e.xual selection, and the part played by the due division of labour between the two s.e.xes, is exceedingly important, and I believe that here we must seek for the most powerful causes which have determined the origin and the historical development of the races of man. (Gen. Morph. ii. 247.) As Darwin, in his exceedingly interesting work, published in 1871, on "The Origin of Man and s.e.xual Selection,"(48) has discussed this subject in the most masterly manner, and has ill.u.s.trated it by most remarkable examples, I refer for further detail to that work.

But now let us look again at two extremely important organic laws which can be explained by the theory of selection, as necessary consequences of natural selection in the struggle for existence. I mean the law of _division of labour_, or _differentiation_, and the law of _progress_, or _perfecting_. When the phenomena due to these two laws first became known, through observation of the historical development, the individual development, and the comparative anatomy of animals and plants, naturalists were inclined to trace them to a direct creative influence.

It was supposed to be part of the plan of the Creator, acting for a definite purpose, in the course of time to develop the forms of animals and plants more and more variously, and to bring them more and more to a state of perfection. We shall evidently make a great advance in the knowledge of nature if we reject this teleological and anthropomorphic conception, and if we can prove the two laws of Division of Labour and Perfecting to be the necessary consequences of natural selection in the struggle for life.

The first great law which follows directly and of necessity from natural selection, is that of _separation_, or _differentiation_, which is frequently called _division of labour_, or _polymorphism_, and which Darwin speaks of as _divergence of character_. (Gen. Morph. ii. 249.) We understand by it the general tendency of all organic individuals to develop themselves more and more diversely, and to deviate from the common primary type. The cause of this general inclination towards differentiation and the formation of heterogeneous forms from h.o.m.ogeneous beginnings is, according to Darwin, simply to be traced to the circ.u.mstance that the struggle for life between every two organisms rages all the more fiercely the nearer the relation in which they stand to one another, or the more nearly alike they are. This is an exceedingly important, and in reality an exceedingly simple relation, but it is usually not duly considered.

It must be obvious to every one, that in a field of a certain size, beside the corn-plants which have been sown, a great number of weeds can exist, and, moreover, in places which could not have been occupied by corn-plants. The more dry and sterile places of the ground, in which no corn-plant would thrive, may still furnish sustenance to weeds of different kinds; and such species and individuals of weeds will more readily be able to exist in such conditions, in proportion as they are suited to adapt themselves to the different parts of the ground. It is the same with animals. It is evident that a much greater number of animal individuals can live together in one and the same limited district, if they are of various and different natures, than if they are all alike. There are trees (for example, the oak) on which a couple of hundred of different species of insects live together. Some feed on the fruits of the tree, others on the leaves, others again on the bark, the root, etc. It would be quite impossible for an equal number of individuals to live on this tree if all were of one species; if, for example, all fed on the bark, or only upon the leaves. Exactly the same is the case in human society. In one and the same small town, only a certain number of workmen can exist, even when they follow different occupations. The division of labour, which is of the greatest use to the whole community, as well as to the individual workman, is a direct consequence of the struggle for life, of natural selection; for this struggle can be sustained more easily the more the activities, and hence, also, the forms of the different individuals deviate from one another. The different function naturally produces its reaction in changing the form, and the physiological division of labour necessarily determines the morphological differentiation, that is, the "divergence of character."(37)

Now, I beg the reader again to remember that all species of animals and plants are variable, and possess the capability of adapting themselves to different places or to local relations. The varieties or races of each species, according to the laws of adaptation, deviate all the more from the original primary species, the greater the difference of the new conditions to which they adapt themselves. If we imagine these varieties-which have proceeded from a common primary form-to be disposed in the shape of a branching, radiating bunch, then those varieties will be best able to exist side by side and propagate which are most distant from one another, which stand at the ends of the series, or at the opposite sides of the bunch. Those forms, on the other hand, occupying a middle position-presenting a state of transition-have the most difficult position in the struggle for life.

The necessaries of life differ most in the two extremes, in the varieties most distant from one another, and consequently these will get into the least serious conflict with one another in the general struggle for life. But the intermediate forms, which have deviated less from the original primary form, require nearly the same necessaries of life as the original form, and therefore, in competing for them, they will have to struggle most with, and be most seriously threatened by, its members.

Consequently, when numerous varieties of a species live side by side on the same spot of the earth, the extremes, or those forms deviating most from one another, can much more easily continue to exist beside one another than the intermediate forms which have to struggle with each of the different extremes. The intermediate forms will not be able to resist, for any length of time, the hostile influences which the extreme forms victoriously overcome. These alone maintain and propagate themselves, and at length cease to be any longer connected with the original primary species through intermediate forms of transition. Thus arise "good species" out of varieties. Thus, then, the struggle for life necessarily favours the general divergence of organic forms, that is, the constant tendency of organisms to form new species. This fact does not rest upon any mystic quality, or upon an unknown formative tendency, but upon the interaction of Inheritance and Adaptation in the struggle for life. As the intermediate forms, that is, the individuals in a state of transition, of the varieties of every species die out and become extinct, the process of divergence constantly goes further, and from the extremes forms develop which we distinguish as new species.

Although all naturalists have been obliged to acknowledge the variability and mutability of all species of animals and plants, yet most of them have hitherto denied that the modification or transformation of the organic form surpa.s.ses the original limit of the characters of the species. Our opponents cling to the proposition-"However far a species may exhibit deviations from its usual form in a collection of varieties, yet the varieties of it are never so distinct from one another as two really good species." This a.s.sertion, which Darwin's opponents usually place at the head of their arguments, is utterly untenable and unfounded. This will become quite clear as soon as we critically compare the various attempts to define the idea of species. No naturalist can answer the question as to what is in reality a "genuine or good species" ("bona species"); yet every systematic naturalist uses this expression every day, and whole libraries have been written on the question as to whether this or that observed form is a species or a variety, whether it is a really good or a bad species. The most general answer to this question used to be the following: "To one species belong all those individuals which agree in all essential characteristics. Essential characteristics of species are those which remain permanent or constant, and never become modified or vary." But as soon as a case occurred in which the characteristic-which had hitherto been considered essential-did become modified, then it was said, "This characteristic is not essential to the species, for essential characteristics never vary." Those who argued thus evidently moved in a circle, and the navete with which this circular method of defining species is laid down in thousands of books as an una.s.sailable truth, and is still constantly repeated, is truly astonis.h.i.+ng.

All other attempts which have been made to arrive at a definite and logical determination of the idea of organic "species" have, like the last, been utterly futile, and led to no results. Considering the nature of the case, it cannot be otherwise. The idea of species is just as truly a relative one and not absolute, as is the idea of variety, genus, family, order, cla.s.s, etc. I have proved this in detail in the criticism of the idea of species in my "General Morphology" (Gen. Morph. ii.

323-364). I will waste no more time on this unsatisfactory discussion, and now only add a few words about the _relation of species to hybridism_. Formerly it was regarded as a dogma, that two good species could never produce hybrids which could reproduce themselves as such.

Those who thus dogmatized almost always appealed to the hybrids of a horse and donkey, the mule and the hinny, which, truly enough, are seldom able to reproduce themselves. But the truth is that such unfruitful hybrids are rare examples, and in the majority of cases hybrids of two totally different species are fruitful and able to reproduce themselves. They can almost always fruitfully mix with one or other of the parent species, and sometimes also among themselves; and in this way completely new forms can originate according to the laws of "mixed transmission by inheritance."

Thus, in fact, _hybridism is a source of the origin of new species_, distinct from the source we have hitherto considered-natural selection.

I have already spoken occasionally of these _hybrid species_ (species hybridae), especially of the hare-rabbit (Lepus Darwinii), which has arisen from the crossing of a male hare and a female rabbit; the goat-sheep (Capra ovina), which has arisen from the pairing of a he-goat and ewe; also the different species of thistles (Cirsium), brambles (Rubus), etc. It is possible that many wild species have originated in this way, as even Linnaeus a.s.sumed. At all events, these hybrid species, which can maintain and propagate themselves as well as pure species, prove that hybridism cannot serve in any way to give an absolute definition to the idea of species.

I have already mentioned (p. 47) that the many vain attempts to define the idea of species theoretically have nothing whatever to do with the practical distinction of species. The extensive practical application of the idea of species, as it is carried out in systematic zoology and botany, is very instructive as furnis.h.i.+ng an example of human folly.

Hitherto, by far the majority of zoologists and botanists, in distinguis.h.i.+ng and describing the different forms of animals and plants, have endeavoured, above all things, to distinguish accurately kindred forms as so many "good species." However, it has been found scarcely possible, in any group, to make an accurate and consistent distinction of such "genuine or good species." There are no two zoologists, no two botanists, who agree in all cases as to which of the nearly related forms of a genus are good species, and which are not. All authors have different views about them. In the genus _Hieracium_, for example, one of the commonest genera of European plants, no less than 300 species have been distinguished in Germany alone. The botanist Fries, however, only admits 106, Koch only 52, as "good species," and others accept scarcely 20. The differences in the species of brambles (Rubus) are equally great. Where one botanist makes more than a hundred species, a second admits only about one half of that number, a third only five or six, or even fewer species. The birds of Germany have long been very accurately known. Bechstein, in his careful "Natural History of German Birds," has distinguished 367 species, L. Reichenbach 379, Meyer and Wolff 406, and Brehm, a clergyman learned in ornithology, distinguishes even more than 900 different species.

Please click Like and leave more comments to support and keep us alive.

RECENTLY UPDATED MANGA

The History of Creation Volume I Part 10 summary

You're reading The History of Creation. This manga has been translated by Updating. Author(s): Ernst Haeckel. Already has 546 views.

It's great if you read and follow any novel on our website. We promise you that we'll bring you the latest, hottest novel everyday and FREE.

BestLightNovel.com is a most smartest website for reading manga online, it can automatic resize images to fit your pc screen, even on your mobile. Experience now by using your smartphone and access to BestLightNovel.com