The Freedom of Science - BestLightNovel.com
You’re reading novel The Freedom of Science Part 26 online at BestLightNovel.com. Please use the follow button to get notification about the latest chapter next time when you visit BestLightNovel.com. Use F11 button to read novel in full-screen(PC only). Drop by anytime you want to read free – fast – latest novel. It’s great if you could leave a comment, share your opinion about the new chapters, new novel with others on the internet. We’ll do our best to bring you the finest, latest novel everyday. Enjoy
It was a solemn hour, pregnant with profound significance, when at midnight at the beginning of this century all the churchbells of the Catholic globe were ringing, and, while everything around was silent, their blessed sound was resounding alone over the earth, over villages and cities, over countries and nations. Grandly there resounded into the whole world, over the heads of the children of men about to enter upon a new century of their history, that the Catholic Church is the Queen in the realm of mind, that she alone preserves infallibly the truths and ideals of which mankind is in quest, by which they are raised above earthly turmoil-those truths and ideals in which the heart and mind of earthly pilgrims find rest and peace on their long journey to the goal of time.
Since she a.s.sumed the mission of Him who said, "I am the Way and the Truth," and, "I am with you all days, even unto the consummation of the world," the Church has travelled a long way through the centuries, has withstood hard times and fierce storms. And she has faithfully preserved for mankind the precious patrimony from G.o.d's hand. And now, at the dawn of new times, her bells proclaimed that she is still alive, holding the old truths in a strong hand. And after another century the bells of the globe will ring again, they will, so we hope-ring more loudly and more forcefully, over the nations. And these bells will also ring over the graves of this present generation, over fallen giants of the forest and over collapsed towers, over mouldy books, and the wreckage left by a culture that the emanc.i.p.ated, fallible human mind created, but which truth did not consecrate. And again the bells will proclaim to a new century that G.o.d, and the world's history, are thinking greater thoughts than the puny child of man is capable of thinking within the narrow compa.s.s of his years and of his surroundings.
FOURTH SECTION. FREEDOM OF TEACHING.
Preliminary Conceptions and Distinctions.
Acquisition and distribution, labour and communication of the fruits of labour, are the two factors that determine the progress of mankind. Thus the precious metal is mined and brought to the surface by the labourer, whence it speeds through the world; thus the faithful missionary journeys into remote countries, to disseminate there the mental treasures acquired by study and hard religious effort. And thus science desires to work, and should work, for the culture and progress of mankind, and this work is pre-eminently its task. To properly pursue this vocation science demands freedom, _freedom in research and teaching_. There is, as we have already pointed out, an important distinction between the two. Although research and teaching are mostly joined, the former only attaining its chief end in teaching, there is a real difference between the two elements; and not unfrequently they are separated. It makes quite a difference whether some one within the four walls of his room studies anarchy, or whether he proceeds to proclaim its principles to the world; it is quite different whether a man embraces atheism for his personal use only, or whether he makes propaganda for it from the pulpit; it makes also a world of difference whether a man is personally convinced that materialism is the sole truth, or whether he proclaims it as a science, and is able to affirm that of the German edition of "Weltratsel" 200,000 copies have been sold, of the English edition about as many, and that a dozen other translations have spread the fundamental notions of monism broadcast through the world (_E. Haeckel_, Monismus u. Naturgesetz). Teaching must be viewed from a different point. Research is a personal function, whereas Teaching is a social one. This fact, of itself, makes it evident that teaching cannot be allowed the same measure of freedom as research, hence that teaching must be confined within narrower limits.
But Freedom is demanded not only for research, but also for teaching, in most cases even an unlimited freedom. It is demanded as an inalienable right of the individual, it is demanded in the name of progress, which can be promoted only by new knowledge. Some countries grant this freedom in their const.i.tutions. Before discussing this demand and its presumptions, we shall have to make clear some preliminary conceptions.
First, the meaning of _freedom of teaching_. How is it precisely to be understood? Freedom in teaching in general means, evidently, exemption from unwarranted restraint in teaching. Teaching, however, to use the words of a great thinker of the past, means _Causare in alio scientiam_, to impart knowledge to some one else (_Thomas Aquinas_, Quaest. disp. De verit. q. XI al.). Thus the pious mother teaches the child truths about G.o.d and Heaven, the school-teacher teaches elementary knowledge, the college-professor teaches science. Teaching is chiefly understood to be the instruction by professional teachers, from grammar school up to university. Hence freedom in teaching does not necessarily refer to scientific matters only; we may also speak of a freedom of teaching in the elementary school. As a rule, however, the term is used in the narrower sense of freedom in teaching science.
Here it may not be amiss to mention further distinctions. As we may distinguish in teaching three essentials, namely, the matter, the method, and the teacher, so there is a corresponding triple freedom of teaching. If we regard the matter, we meet with the demand, that no one be excluded in an unjust way from exercising his right to teach, that no single party should have the monopoly of teaching: the right to found free universities also belongs here. It is part of the freedom of teaching. As it has relation to the state, we shall return to this point later on. A second freedom, which might be called methodological, concerns the choice of the method. This is naturally subject to considerable restraint; not only because the academic teacher may frequently have to get along without desirable paraphernalia, but also because of the commission he receives with his appointment, wherein his field and scope are prescribed. This is necessary for the purpose of the university; the students are to acquire the varied knowledge needed later on in their vocations of clergyman, lawyer, teacher, or physician. There is frequent complaint that this freedom in method is abused to a certain extent, that the students are taught many fragments of science with thoroughness, but too little of that which they actually need later on; they are trained too much for theoretical work and not enough for the practical vocation. Thus there is limitation here, too. But this is not the freedom in teaching which occupies the centre of interest to-day.
The trophy for which the battle is waged is the freedom relating to the _subject_ of teaching; we shall term it "doctrinal" freedom in teaching: Shall the representative of science be permitted to promulgate any view he has formed? Even if that view conflicts with general religious or moral convictions, with the social order? Or must this freedom be curbed? This is the question.(19)
Obviously, teaching need not always be done _verbally_, it can be done also by _writing_. The professor lectures in the cla.s.srooms, but he may also expound his theories in books; this latter the private scholar may also do. In this way _Plato_ and _Aristotle_ and the Fathers are still teaching by their writings, though their lips have long been silent. True, this way of teaching has not the force of the spoken word, vibrating with personal conviction, but it reaches farther out, with telling effect upon ma.s.ses and remote circles. Thus, freedom in teaching includes also the freedom to print and publish scientific theories, hence it includes part of the _freedom of the press_; in its full meaning, however, the freedom of the press relates also to unscientific periodicals, especially newspapers.
A counterpart to the freedom in teaching is presented by the _freedom in learning_. It concerns the student, and may consist of the right granted to the "academic citizen" to choose at his discretion, but within the restrictions set by his studies, his university, his teachers, and his curriculum.
Chapter I. Freedom Of Teaching And Ethics.
Now for a closer examination of the problem of freedom of teaching, from the point of _general ethics_, not of law. This is an important distinction, not seldom overlooked. The former point of view deals with freedom in teaching only in as far as regulated or circ.u.mscribed by ethical principles, by the moral principles of conscience, without regard to state-laws or other positive rules. The freedom in teaching as determined by governmental decrees may be called freedom of teaching by state-right. It may happen that the state does not prohibit the dissemination of doctrines which may be forbidden by reason and conscience, for instance, atheistical doctrine. There may be immoral products of art not prohibited by the state; yet ethics cannot grant license to p.o.r.nography. The state grants the liberty of changing from one creed to another, or of declaring one's self an atheist; yet this does not justify the act before the conscience. The statutes do not forbid everything that is morally impermissible; their aim is directed only at offences against the good of the commonwealth. Moreover, even such offences may not be prohibited by statute, for the simple reason that the enactment of such laws may be impossible on account of the complexion of legislative bodies, or because of other conditions.
We will now take the ethical position and try to judge the freedom of teaching from this point of view. First of all, we shall have to explain the _social character_ of teaching and the _responsibility_ attached thereto. We start again with the meaning of freedom of teaching. It demands that the communication of scientific opinions should not be restrained in unwarranted manner. "In unwarranted manner"; because, manifestly, not all bars are to be removed; no one will a.s.sert that a man may teach things he knows to be false. Every activity, including scientific activity, must conform to truth and morals. Hence there is only the question to determine, when is freedom in teaching morally reprehensible, and when not; which are the bars that must not be transgressed, and which bars may be disregarded? Is it allowed or not to teach any opinion, if the teacher subjectively believes it to be true?
Here the views differ. However, one thing at present is clear:
Freedom of Teaching is Necessary.
Also in respect to method. Even the teacher in public and grammar schools, though minutely guided by the plan of instruction, must be granted, by the demands of pedagogy, a certain liberty; he should be free to arrange and to try many things. Only where individual spontaneity is given play will love for work be aroused, which in turn stimulates devotion to the cause and makes for success. This applies with even greater force to the college-professor, in respect to method, course of instruction, subject, and the results of his research. He must be free to communicate them, without consideration for unwarranted prejudices, or for private and party interests.
If the scientist were condemned to do nothing but repeat the old things, without change and variance, without improvement and correction, without new additions and discoveries, all alertness and impulse would disappear; but his alacrity and ardour will increase, if allowed to contribute to progress, if a.s.sured beforehand of publicity for the new solutions he hopes to find, if allowed to promulgate new discoveries.
This freedom is demanded, even more imperatively, by the vocation of science to work for the progress of mankind, primarily for the intellectual and through this for the general progress. The demand in behalf of the individual is even more urgent in behalf of science at large: no standing still, ever onward to new knowledge and the enrichment of the mind, to moral uplift, to a beautifying of life-and ultimately to the glorification of G.o.d! For, verily, the purpose of the whole universe is the glory of the Creator. Glory is given to Him by the world of stars, as they speed through s.p.a.ce, conforming to His laws; glory is given to Him by the dewdrop, as it reflects the rays of the morning sun; glory is given to Him by the b.u.t.terfly, as it unfolds the brilliancy of colours received from His hand. The chief glory of all is given to Him by the reason-endowed human mind, developing its powers ever more fully, the crowning achievement of visible creation, wherein G.o.d's wisdom reflects brighter than the sun in the morning-dew. And for this is needed the freedom of scientific progress, which would be impossible without a freedom in teaching.
And this applies not only to fixed conclusions; it must also be permitted, within admissible bounds, to teach scientific _hypotheses_. Science needs them for its progress; they are the buds that burst forth into blossoms. Had men like _Copernicus_, _Newton_, _Huygens_, not been free to propound their hypotheses, the sun would still revolve around the earth, we still would have _Ptolemy's_ revolution of the spheres, and the results of optical science would be denied us.
A Twofold Freedom of Teaching and Its Presumption.
There cannot be any doubt that science must have freedom in teaching. But of what kind? One that is necessary and suitable. Yes, but what kind of freedom is that? Here is the crux of the question. Now we are again at the boundary line where we stood, when defining the freedom of science in general, at the parting of the ways of two contrary conceptions of man.
One is the Christian idea, and also that of unbia.s.sed reason. Man is a limited creature, depending on G.o.d, on truth and moral law, at the same time dependent on social life, hence also dependent on social order and authority; consequently he cannot claim independence, but only the freedom compatible with his position. Therefore the barriers demanded by truth and by the duty of belief are set to his research; hence his freedom in teaching can only be the one permitted by his social position; personal perception of truth _and_ consideration for the welfare of mankind will be the barriers of this freedom.
This view is opposed by another, claiming full independence for both research and teaching, a claim prompted by the modern philosophy of _free humanity_, which sees in man an autonomous being, who needs only follow the immanent impulses of his own individuality; and this especially in that activity which is deemed the most perfect, the pursuit of science: this hypostatized collective-being of the highest human pursuit is also to be the supreme bearer of autonomism. As a matter of course this results in the claim for unlimited freedom in teaching, a freedom we shall term _liberal_: in communicating his scientific view the scientist need merely be guided by his perception of truth, without any considerations for external authorities or interests, provided his communication is a scientific one, viz., observing the usual form of scientific teaching.
This latter limitation is usually added, because this freedom is to apply to the teaching of _science_ only; to the popular presentation of scientific views, appealing directly to the ma.s.ses, such a freedom is not always conceded.
"Research," we are told, "demands full freedom, with no other barrier but its own desire for truth, hence the academic teacher who teaches in the capacity of an investigator is likewise not to know any barriers but his inner truthfulness and propriety." "In this sense we demand to-day freedom in teaching for our universities. The freedom of the scientist and of the academic teacher must not be constrained by any patented truth, nor by faint-hearted consideration. We let the word of the Bible comfort us: 'if this doctrine is of G.o.d, it will endure; if not, it will pa.s.s away' " (_Kaufmann_). Whatever the academic teacher produces from his subjective veracity must be inviolable; he may proclaim it as truth, regardless of consequences. "The searching scientist," so says another, "must consider only the one question: What is truth? But inasmuch as there cannot be research without communication(?), we must go a step further: the teaching, too, must not be restricted. The scientific writer has to heed but one consideration: How can I present the things exactly as I perceive them, in the clearest and most precise manner?" (_Paulsen_).
"Scientific research and the communication of its results must, conformable to its purpose, be independent of any consideration not innate in the scientific method itself,-hence independent of the traditions and prejudices of the ma.s.ses, independent of authorities and social groups, independent of interested parties.
That this independence is indispensable needs no demonstration."
"Nor can any limitation of the freedom of research and teaching be deduced from the official position of the scientist or teacher"
(_Von Amira_). Just as soon as he begins his research according to scientific method, _i.e._, adapts his thoughts to scientific rules, customs, and postulates, he may question Christianity, G.o.d, everything; neither state nor Church must object, no matter if thousands are led astray.
This freedom is pre-eminently claimed for philosophical and religious thought, for ideas relating to views of the world and the foundations of social order; because only in this province is absolute freedom of teaching likely to be seriously refused. In mathematics and the natural sciences, in philology and kindred sciences, there is hardly occasion for it; there only petty disputes occur, differences among compet.i.tors, things that do not reach beyond the precinct of the learned fraternity. Whether one is for or against the theory of three-dimensional s.p.a.ce, for or against the theory of ions and the like, all that touches very little on the vital questions of mankind; but the case is quite different when it comes to publicly advocating the abolition of private property, to the preaching of polygamy: it is here where great clashes threaten. Here, also, there enter into the plan the social powers, whose duty it is to s.h.i.+eld the highest possessions of human society against wanton attack.
Nevertheless the demand is for unlimited freedom in teaching. What, then, are the arguments used in giving to this exceptional claim the semblance of justification? This shall be the first question.
Unlimited Freedom in Teaching not Demanded.
1. Not by Veracity.
Veracity is appealed to first; it obligates the teacher, so it is said, to announce his own convictions unreservedly, for to "deny one's own convictions would offend against one of the most positive principles of morals"; hence the academic teacher could not grant to the state the right to set a barrier in this respect, "it would be a violation of the duty of veracity, which is innate to the teacher's office" (_Von Amira_).
Was it realized in making this claim what the duty of truthfulness really demands? This duty is complied with when one is not untruthful, that is to say, does not state something to be his opinion when secretly he believes the contrary to be true; to force him to do this would of course be instigating untruthfulness. Truthfulness, however, does not require any one to speak out publicly what he thinks; one may be silent. Or is cautious silence untruthfulness? It is oftentimes prudence, but not untruthfulness. There is a considerable difference between thinking and communicating thought, even to the scientist.
Or is the scientist _obliged_, for instance, to proclaim publicly views he has formed contrary to the prevailing principles of morals,-views he calls the "results of his research," so that mankind at last may learn the truth? Was _Nietzsche_ in duty bound to proclaim to the wide world his revolutionary ideas? Any sober-minded man might have told him he need not worry about this duty. Has the teacher of science this duty? How will he prove it? How are they going to prove that it is inc.u.mbent upon an atheistic college-professor to teach his atheism also to others? Or, must he teach that the fundamental principles of Christian marriage are untenable, if this has become his personal opinion? Is it, perhaps, impossible for him to refrain from such teaching in the lectures he is appointed to give? This view will mostly prove a delusion. A conscientious examination of his opinion would convince him that he, too, had better abandon it, since it is merely an aberration of his mind. But let us a.s.sume that he could neither correct his views nor refrain from proclaiming them, that he would declare: "I should lie if, in discussing the question in how far this or that public inst.i.tution is morally sanctioned, I were to halt before certain inst.i.tutions; for instance if, having the moral conviction that monarchy is a morally objectionable inst.i.tution, I omitted to say so" (_Th. Lipps_).
Well, he has the option to change his branch of teaching, or to resign his office; he is not indispensable, no one forces him to retain his office.
Indeed, he owes it to _truthfulness_ to leave his post the very instant he finds he is not able to occupy it in a beneficial way; he owes it to _honesty_ to yield his position, if he has lost the proper relation to religion, state, and the people, to whom his position is to render service.
2. Not the Duty of Science.